Well-ordering principle

Statement that all non empty subsets of positive numbers contains a least element

In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty subset of positive integers contains a least element.[1] In other words, the set of positive integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which x {\displaystyle x} precedes y {\displaystyle y} if and only if y {\displaystyle y} is either x {\displaystyle x} or the sum of x {\displaystyle x} and some positive integer (other orderings include the ordering 2 , 4 , 6 , . . . {\displaystyle 2,4,6,...} ; and 1 , 3 , 5 , . . . {\displaystyle 1,3,5,...} ).

The phrase "well-ordering principle" is sometimes taken to be synonymous with the "well-ordering theorem". On other occasions it is understood to be the proposition that the set of integers { , 2 , 1 , 0 , 1 , 2 , 3 , } {\displaystyle \{\ldots ,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,\ldots \}} contains a well-ordered subset, called the natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.

Properties

Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second-order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem. For example:

  • In Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic and related systems, and indeed in most (not necessarily formal) mathematical treatments of the well-ordering principle, the principle is derived from the principle of mathematical induction, which is itself taken as basic.
  • Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers, and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete (again, either as an axiom or a theorem about the real number system), i.e., every bounded (from below) set has an infimum, then also every set A {\displaystyle A} of natural numbers has an infimum, say a {\displaystyle a^{*}} . We can now find an integer n {\displaystyle n^{*}} such that a {\displaystyle a^{*}} lies in the half-open interval ( n 1 , n ] {\displaystyle (n^{*}-1,n^{*}]} , and can then show that we must have a = n {\displaystyle a^{*}=n^{*}} , and n {\displaystyle n^{*}} in A {\displaystyle A} .
  • In axiomatic set theory, the natural numbers are defined as the smallest inductive set (i.e., set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation). One can (even without invoking the regularity axiom) show that the set of all natural numbers n {\displaystyle n} such that " { 0 , , n } {\displaystyle \{0,\ldots ,n\}} is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered.

In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set S {\displaystyle S} , assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction. It is known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method[citation needed] and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent".

Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane wrote in A Survey of Modern Algebra that this property, like the least upper bound axiom for real numbers, is non-algebraic; i.e., it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers (which form an ordered integral domain).

Example applications

The well-ordering principle can be used in the following proofs.

Prime factorization

Theorem: Every integer greater than one can be factored as a product of primes. This theorem constitutes part of the Prime Factorization Theorem.

Proof (by well-ordering principle). Let C {\displaystyle C} be the set of all integers greater than one that cannot be factored as a product of primes. We show that C {\displaystyle C} is empty.

Assume for the sake of contradiction that C {\displaystyle C} is not empty. Then, by the well-ordering principle, there is a least element n C {\displaystyle n\in C} ; n {\displaystyle n} cannot be prime since a prime number itself is considered a length-one product of primes. By the definition of non-prime numbers, n {\displaystyle n} has factors a , b {\displaystyle a,b} , where a , b {\displaystyle a,b} are integers greater than one and less than n {\displaystyle n} . Since a , b < n {\displaystyle a,b<n} , they are not in C {\displaystyle C} as n {\displaystyle n} is the smallest element of C {\displaystyle C} . So, a , b {\displaystyle a,b} can be factored as products of primes, where a = p 1 p 2 . . . p k {\displaystyle a=p_{1}p_{2}...p_{k}} and b = q 1 q 2 . . . q l {\displaystyle b=q_{1}q_{2}...q_{l}} , meaning that n = p 1 p 2 . . . p k q 1 q 2 . . . q l {\displaystyle n=p_{1}p_{2}...p_{k}\cdot q_{1}q_{2}...q_{l}} , a product of primes. This contradicts the assumption that n C {\displaystyle n\in C} , so the assumption that C {\displaystyle C} is nonempty must be false.[2]

Integer summation

Theorem: 1 + 2 + 3 + . . . + n = n ( n + 1 ) 2 {\displaystyle 1+2+3+...+n={\frac {n(n+1)}{2}}} for all positive integers n {\displaystyle n} .

Proof. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that the above theorem is false. Then, there exists a non-empty set of positive integers C = { n N 1 + 2 + 3 + . . . + n n ( n + 1 ) 2 } {\displaystyle C=\{n\in \mathbb {N} \mid 1+2+3+...+n\neq {\frac {n(n+1)}{2}}\}} . By the well-ordering principle, C {\displaystyle C} has a minimum element c {\displaystyle c} such that when n = c {\displaystyle n=c} , the equation is false, but true for all positive integers less than c {\displaystyle c} . The equation is true for n = 1 {\displaystyle n=1} , so c > 1 {\displaystyle c>1} ; c 1 {\displaystyle c-1} is a positive integer less than c {\displaystyle c} , so the equation holds for c 1 {\displaystyle c-1} as it is not in C {\displaystyle C} . Therefore,

1 + 2 + 3 + . . . + ( c 1 ) = ( c 1 ) c 2 1 + 2 + 3 + . . . + ( c 1 ) + c = ( c 1 ) c 2 + c = c 2 c 2 + 2 c 2 = c 2 + c 2 = c ( c + 1 ) 2 {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}1+2+3+...+(c-1)&={\frac {(c-1)c}{2}}\\1+2+3+...+(c-1)+c&={\frac {(c-1)c}{2}}+c\\&={\frac {c^{2}-c}{2}}+{\frac {2c}{2}}\\&={\frac {c^{2}+c}{2}}\\&={\frac {c(c+1)}{2}}\end{aligned}}}
which shows that the equation holds for c {\displaystyle c} , a contradiction. So, the equation must hold for all positive integers.[2]

References

  1. ^ Apostol, Tom (1976). Introduction to Analytic Number Theory. New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 13. ISBN 0-387-90163-9.
  2. ^ a b Lehman, Eric; Meyer, Albert R; Leighton, F Tom. Mathematics for Computer Science (PDF). Retrieved 2 May 2023.